THE Global Justice Movement Website

THE Global Justice Movement Website
This is the "Global Justice Movement" (dot org) we refer to in the title of this blog.

Wednesday, March 19, 2025

Persons, Things, and Personalism

A while back we put together a short video to explain the idea of economic democracy along personalist lines.  Titled “People and Things,” it took a sort of “Dr. Suessy” approach, putting some very complex ideas in hopefully simple rhyming language to try and present them in a coherent and comprehensible way.  It was (and is) pretty good, but because it is both brief and simplified, doesn’t get into deeper meanings and implications.


 

The question is, What do we mean by “people”?  In context, it means persons . . . but that would sound a little stilted to title a short video “Persons and Things.”

According to one legal definition, a person is “[a] man [okay, human being — ed.] considered according to the rank he holds in society, with all the rights to which the place he holds entitles him, and the duties which it imposes.  A human being considered as capable of having rights and of being charged with duties; while a ‘thing’ is the object over which rights may be exercised.”  (We ignore for the sake of the argument “artificial persons,” which are “legal fictions” for convenience or expedience and are not persons by nature.

Defining person in this way raises another question.  What does it mean to say a man — or a human being, strictly speaking — is “considered according to the rank he holds in society, with all the rights to which the place he holds entitles him, and the duties which it imposes”?  Does that mean we as persons (or human beings) are purely social beings?  Or is society an unnatural construct, holding us back?


 

Actually, we fall into a different category, which Aristotle called “political.”  Human beings are individuals who live by nature in consciously organized social orders.  Nothing human is purely individual, any more than anything human is purely social.  We are individuals who are also social — persons, not things.  If human beings were purely individual or purely social as some claim, we could not be persons.  We would be things.

All persons have a determinable nature, that is, have free will, and a social identity — persons own things.  All things have a determinate nature, that is, do not have free will, and do not have a social identity — things are owned by persons.  Persons have rights by nature, although things — artificial persons — may have rights delegated to them from persons.

This leads us into the discussion on persons from the book, Economic Personalism (pp. 8-9.).


 

To explain, human beings are neither isolated individuals nor undifferentiated members of a collective. We are persons who by nature associate with one another in a consciously structured environment called the pólis, hence political.

While the pólis can be structured to encourage either virtue or vice, it is neither virtuous nor vicious in and of itself. We therefore speak of the social environment as being made up of structures of virtue or structures of vice or sin. Society may encourage us one way or another, but which way we go is ultimately our personal and joint responsibility, as is the structuring of the pólis itself.

It is important to realize that human beings are not only rational and political, but tool makers and users. There is, of course, also the irrational and emotional side of human beings, but since we are discussing personalism and the primacy of reason over irrationality, we will ignore it for the sake of the argument.


 

Consistent with human nature, then, we consciously structure and maintain our environment in both its physical and its social aspects to provide the opportunity and means to secure our wellbeing. Our physical environment, including the natural world around us, also consists of infrastructure, houses, factories, stores, roads, dams, bridges, and so on, that we possess individually or in association with others.


 

Our social environment consists of a vast network of invisible structures comprising the common good that each person as such is supposed to possess in its entirety. This network includes laws, customs, traditions, and other institutions (“social habits”), and social tools such as money and credit, tax systems, even language and the State.

Both the physical and the social environment are tools by means of which the human person carries on the process of living. The process of living consists not only of providing for one’s (and one’s family’s) survival and security, but furthermore by becoming virtuous, thereby becoming more fully human.


 

It is by means of these social tools that each person as a political animal satisfies not only his individual wants and needs, but his social wants and needs (i.e., domestic and civil interpersonal relationships). Preferably this is done in a way that also assists each person in becoming virtuous, that is, more fully human.

In satisfying individual wants and needs within a social framework there must also be no harm done to others or to the common good, and ideally what is done should indirectly benefit the whole of society. To participate fully in society, then, each person must have full access to those invisible structures of the common good, the tools for living in society.

Therein lies what may very well be the greatest immediate problem of the modern age. It underlies all social problems that prevent or inhibit each person developing more fully as a human being.

That problem is the inability of many people to satisfy their individual material wants and needs in a way that respects their own dignity, does not offend or harm the dignity of others, and benefits society, or at least does no harm. This is because most people have been stripped of power, and thus of control over their own lives.

#30#