Yes, that’s “expedience,” not “expedients.” We didn’t misspell. The issue we’re looking at today is the
question of when expedience is allowed, so that you may employ allowed
expedients. Yesterday we contrasted the
clear evil of killing an innocent person for the presumably greater good, with
the more ambiguous situation in which someone’s only recourse to death is to
steal to stay alive.
Utopia of the Usurers? |
As you might expect, there is a “Catch-22” in this
“permission to steal.” The needy
individual may incur no moral guilt,
but the social order is such a great good that certain bad things are permitted
to maintain order, while certain good things are forbidden for the same reason.
Usury, for example — the taking of a
profit when no profit has been generated — is a great evil. Profit-taking is in and of itself, however, is
a very great good, only becoming “evil” (despite the insistence of the
socialists) when no profit has been made.
Pullman Strike, 1894 |
Modern corporate finance and (more especially) the consumer
credit industry are, however, based firmly on the presumed need to take a
profit whether or not profit has been made. This extends even to the presumably “just”
demands of workers for fixed wage and benefits packages sufficient to meet the
needs of them and their dependents . . . whether or not they produce goods and
services of equivalent value to the wages and benefits they receive.
Thus, even though it is a great evil, usury — a form of
theft, and thus a violation of private property — must be allowed to continue, at least in the
present condition of society, even though the usurer incurs grave moral guilt
when he has another viable choice. This
is because simply abolishing usury in all its forms unilaterally and without
changing the basic structures of the modern financial system would destroy
civilization. Yes, it would. Don’t kid yourself.
Paradoxically, stealing from the superabundance of another —
for which the taker does not incur
moral guilt — must not be allowed! That is because if simply taking what one
needed from another became the accepted and ordinary way of obtaining the
necessities of life, society would collapse. That’s also why Leo XIII taught that in
extreme cases the State may make a redistribution: allowing people simply to
take what they need would irreparably harm the common good. (Rerum
Novarum, § 22.)
Private property is one of the pillars of the social order,
along with life and liberty. If anyone
could take what he wanted from the goods of another, the productive would be
punished by not being allowed to profit by their industry, while the lazy and
shiftless would be rewarded. People
would soon only produce at the point of a gun, as became obvious in the former
Soviet Union. Does this mean that there
is no recourse, that mankind is locked into unjust social structures for all
eternity?
Of course not. As
Pius XI made clear
throughout his pontificate, each human person has the power (meaning the right)
and the duty to organize with others when the institutions of the social order
are flawed to an intolerable degree. We
do not simply abolish an evil and prevent it with the coercive power of the
State. On the contrary, we first
convince others that a more rationally structured social order is desirable,
then work to bring it about. The unjust institution — such as usury or
widespread poverty — is either reformed or falls of its own dead weight,
replaced by a better institution. (Vide Rev. William J. Ferrree, S.M.,
Ph.D., The Act of Social Justice.
Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 1942.)
"I am the State" |
Many people, however, find this “act of social justice” —
organizing for the common good in order to effect beneficial change in our
institutions — too slow or presume it to be ineffective. They demand that the State take charge of as
much as possible in order to implement instant social change — enforced, as we
might expect, at the point of a gun: the police power of the State. This ultimately results in the deification of
the State, and inevitably a joining of Church and State in some fashion,
whether through the establishment of an official State church (and thus under
the control of State bureaucrats, and manipulated for political purposes) or
the elimination of competing faiths, leaving the State the only “religious”
body.
Hank Plantagenet, Jr. |
This, then, was the whole issue between Archbishop Thomas
and King Henry — you knew we’d get around to it eventually. In the Middle Ages the Catholic Church had “from time immemorial” certain rights and
privileges on which the civil power — the State — could not encroach. Often, of course, the State had interfered in these matters, with
consequent repercussions, both serious and, in some instances, almost
ludicrous. There were also not a few
worldly ecclesiastics who sought to curry favor with the civil authorities by
asserting that the princes of this world ruled by “divine right,” thereby
muddying the waters even more.
For example, the whole Guelph and Ghibbeline struggle in
Italy and Germany, which spilled over on occasion into France and England, was a struggle between civil
authorities who wanted to take over the Church and use it for their own ends,
and ecclesiastical authorities who wanted to use the spiritual power of the
Church to set things right in the civil sphere, backed by the coercive power of
the State. Once that struggle was
decided, the Guelphs and Ghibbelines (and their spiritual descendants)
continued fighting amongst themselves to decide how Church and State were to relate to each other once the
separation was effected.