One of the things that strikes the reader of what is perhaps
G.K. Chesterton’s greatest book, Saint
Thomas Aquinas: The “Dumb Ox”, is the fact that so little of it is actually
about Aquinas. A rough estimate reveals
that barely a quarter of the text deals with Aquinas himself — and even that
seems to focus more on other people in Aquinas’s life or who are important for
understanding the contemporary situation.
Practically none of it deals with theology.
Manichean Dualism: the Double Mind of Man |
The first paradox is that, as noted, it becomes apparent
that the book isn’t really about Aquinas as the title would suggest. Instead, it is about the thought of Aquinas. As Chesterton stated in his “Introductory
Note”: “I can hardly say much of the philosopher, beyond showing that he had a
philosophy. I have only, so to speak,
given samples of that philosophy.”
(Chesterton, The Dumb Ox, op. cit.,
12.)
The Primacy of the Intellect, not the Will |
Expressed “negatively,” the first principle of reason is the
law or principle of contradiction: that nothing can both “be” and “not be” at
the same time under the same conditions.
Expressed “positively,” this is the law or principle of identity: that
which is true is as true, and is true in the same way, as everything else that
is true.
Denial of this first principle of reason is rooted in the
idea that the natural law either does not exist, or is based on something other
than human nature itself. As Mortimer
Adler summarized this error in his book, Ten
Philosophical Mistakes,
Adler: denial of human nature an error. |
Or, as John Paul II said in Fides et Ratio (keeping in mind that the natural law based on God’s
Nature self-realized in His Intellect and reflected in human nature is
therefore discernible by reason alone), “the legitimate distinction between the two forms of learning
became more and more a fateful separation. . . . [One] of the many consequences
of this separation was an ever-deeper mistrust with regard to reason itself.”
We then come across a third paradox, that the book is more
about the modern world’s rejection of the thought of Aquinas than about the
thought of Aquinas. About this time we
also realize that perhaps the most paradoxical thing of all about the book is
that it can be about so many things at once, and yet not contradict itself on
any significant point.
Understanding this third paradox is key to understanding
what Chesterton was doing. In every case
where he described the opponents of Aquinas, there is a clear parallel with today’s
situation. We see this in the conflict
Aquinas had with the Medieval equivalents of the Traditionalists and the
Modernists, and with the basic philosophies that manifest as socialism and
theosophy in the modern world.
Aristotle incognito, after being rediscovered. |
First, of course, the translations came from Islamic
sources. That was suspicious in and of
itself. Then there was the fact that (at
least in a certain way and of certain types of Muslims) a Muslim who became a
good Aristotelian became a bad Muslim — the work of Ibn Khaldûn, the great
Islamic philosopher who reconciled Mohammed and Aristotle was still in the
future. Islam was, at that point, very
much a will-based faith, at least in its popular aspects, something strongly in
evidence today among extremist sects. As
Chesterton somewhat simplistically put it,
“[W]e may say broadly of the
Moslem philosophers, that those who became good philosophers became bad
Moslems. It is not altogether unnatural
that many bishops and doctors feared that the Thomists might become good
philosophers and bad Christians. But
there were also many, of the strict school of Plato and Augustine, who stoutly
denied that they were even good philosophers.
Between these two rather incongruous passions, the love of Plato and the
fear of Mahomet, there was a moment when the prospects of any Aristotelian
culture in Christendom looked very dark indeed.” (Chesterton, The Dumb Ox, op. cit., 85.)
Dominic de Guzmán the Rationalist |
“The Mystic is right in saying
that the relation of God and Man is essentially a love-story; the pattern and
type of all love-stories. The Dominican
rationalist is equally right in saying that the intellect is at home in the
topmost heavens and that the appetite for truth may outlast and devour all the
duller appetites of man.” (Ibid., 74.)
Worse, due almost certainly to the wild distortions of the
Fraticelli, the Franciscans and Dominicans were seen as overthrowing the proper
order of society. As Chesterton
described the situation,
“[S]ome men had a very vivid
feeling that everything was breaking up; and that all the recent experiments or
excesses were part of the same social dissolution; and there were two things
that such men regarded as signs of ruin; one was the awful apparition of
Aristotle out of the East, a sort of Greek god supported by Arabian
worshippers; and the other was the new freedom of the Friars. It was the opening of the monastery and the
scattering of the monks to wander over the world. The general feeling that they wandered like
sparks from a furnace hitherto contained; the furnace of the abnormal love of
God: the sense that they would utterly unbalance the common people with the
counsels of perfection; that they would drift into being demagogues.” (Ibid., 74.)
Knox: an excess of charity threatens unity. |
Nevertheless, as history proved, Aquinas successfully
defended both Aristotle and the Friars against the hysteria of the social
conservatives — as reported by Chesterton, bearing a suspicious resemblance to
the way that he and Belloc defended distributism and Catholicism against the
capitalist and Anglican establishment of the early twentieth century. No sooner had Aquinas succeeded in this,
however, then another, far greater threat appeared, those whom Chesterton
referred to as Manichees, and which we have no difficulty in recognizing as
Modernists (“Moderns”) who have surrendered to New Age reinvented religion and
socialist economic and political theory, which Chesterton epitomized as
astrology and Communism.