We had a discussion the week before last about how to
understand what the pope is saying. The
problem is that it seems everyone from President Obama on up (cf. the inverted
pyramid structure for JBM and JBL; the real leader is on the bottom, not the top)
hears precisely whatever he or she wants desperately to hear, whether for good
or for ill.
Take, for example, the concept of “infallibility.” A lot of Catholics have almost as much
trouble with this as non-Catholics. It’s
not an easy thing to understand if you approach it from the wrong assumptions.
For example, you have to keep in mind that “infallibility”
means that Catholics believe the pope has the power to discern truth infallibly
in matters regarding faith and morals. This does not extend to how he may
express it, or (more usually) how others understand it. It doesn’t necessarily mean what you want it
to mean, what you think it means, or what you need it to mean to support your
position.
Infallibility doesn’t mean that something is true because the pope says so; rather, the pope says something because it is true. Then he has the fun of trying to make it clear to the rest of us, especially Catholics. This can be difficult, because all of us, the pope included, are fallible human beings, and do not see things clearly as human beings this side of heaven. As Saint Paul reminded us,
“We see now through a glass in a dark manner: but then face to face. Now I know in part: but then I shall know even as I am known. And now there remain faith, hope, and charity, these three: but the greatest of these is charity.”
Infallibility doesn’t mean that something is true because the pope says so; rather, the pope says something because it is true. Then he has the fun of trying to make it clear to the rest of us, especially Catholics. This can be difficult, because all of us, the pope included, are fallible human beings, and do not see things clearly as human beings this side of heaven. As Saint Paul reminded us,
“We see now through a glass in a dark manner: but then face to face. Now I know in part: but then I shall know even as I am known. And now there remain faith, hope, and charity, these three: but the greatest of these is charity.”
Now, some pope or other said something to the effect that
trying to wriggle out of something in an encyclical because it wasn’t declared ex cathedra as “officially infallible” is
a mistake because what is taught in the encyclicals has already been taught as
infallible in many cases. There are, of
course, prudential applications of infallible principles in the encyclicals as
well, which is what confuses a lot of people.
They tend to assume that everything
is infallible, or nothing.
For example, the infallible teaching of the Church with
respect to the means of making a living and “doing something” about the growing
wealth gap is very general: every child, woman, and man has an equal right of
access to the means of gaining an adequate and secure income.
This does not mean that everyone has a right to an adequate
and secure income, however — yet that is the way it has been interpreted by
many people. Frankly, the income may not
exist for people to receive! How, then,
could anyone have a right to something that doesn’t even exist? They can’t.
This is where the wisdom of the popes comes in — and the
oversimplifications many people force on what they say:
1) If the opportunity exists, everyone has an equal right to
engage in productive activity, whether through labor or capital ownership. As Saint Paul said, “He who does not work,
neither shall he eat.” (That, by the
way, is a very good summary of Say’s Law of Markets.)
2) If the opportunity exists, but an individual is not able
to take advantage of the opportunity for some valid reason, others should, in
charity, give him what he needs. If the
need is “extreme,” this becomes due in justice, and the State may make an
additional tax levy to redistribute a measure of wealth until the extreme need
passes. (In social justice, of course,
people have the additional duty of organizing to reform the social order so
that the cause of the extreme need no longer exists.)
2a) The State should carry out the redistribution on a
temporary basis, and only as long as the emergency lasts. Individuals who take what they need directly
from the surplus of others do not incur moral guilt, but they must be punished
under human law because simply taking what you need sets a bad example and undermines
the social order.
3) If opportunity does not exist, the State must
redistribute enough wealth to keep people alive as an expedient, while people
organize and work to create opportunity.
If people acting on their own, individually and in free association with
others, are unable to create opportunity, the State may step in and assist as
an expedient.
3a) State action does not mean artificial job creation, but
the removal of artificial barriers that prevent or inhibit productive
activity. Except as an expedient in an
emergency, the State must not impose desired results, but create and maintain
the environment within which people can meet their own needs through their own
efforts. As Leo XIII explained,
“Man’s
needs do not die out, but forever recur; although satisfied today, they demand
fresh supplies for tomorrow. Nature accordingly must have given to man a source
that is stable and remaining always with him, from which he might look to draw
continual supplies. And this stable condition of things he finds solely in the
earth and its fruits. There is no need to bring in the State. Man precedes the
State, and possesses, prior to the formation of any State, the right of
providing for the substance of his body.” (Rerum
Novarum, § 7.)
As you can see, this is extremely nuanced, with a great deal
of prudential applications mixed in with the infallible principle. This is why almost every pope since Leo XIII
has carefully instructed people to interpret what is in the encyclicals in
light of Thomist philosophy. Trying to
interpret the encyclicals through the filter of any other philosophy
necessarily twists and distorts matters — which is what G. K. Chesterton warned
about in Saint Thomas Aquinas: “The Dumb
Ox” (1933), his short biographical sketch of Aquinas:
“Since
the modern world began in the sixteenth century, nobody’s system of philosophy
has really corresponded to everybody’s sense of reality; to what, if left to
themselves, common men would call common sense. Each started with a paradox; a
peculiar point of view demanding the sacrifice of what they would call a sane
point of view. That is the one thing common to Hobbes and Hegel, to Kant and
Bergson, to Berkeley and William James. A man had to believe something that no
normal man would believe, if it were suddenly propounded to his simplicity; as
that law is above right, or right is outside reason, or things are only as we
think them, or everything is relative to a reality that is not there. The
modern philosopher claims, like a sort of confidence man, that if once we will
grant him this, the rest will be easy; he will straighten out the world, if
once he is allowed to give this one twist to the mind.” (G. K. Chesterton, Saint Thomas Aquinas: The “Dumb Ox”. New
York: Image Books, 1956, 145-146.)
This is also what Fulton J. Sheen warned against in his
first book, God and Intelligence in
Modern Philosophy (1925) — to which Chesterton wrote the introduction.
These are not easy concepts, but the simplifiers do no one,
least of all themselves, any favors.
This is one reason why the interfaith Center for Economic and Social
Justice (CESJ) has republished Fulton Sheen’s Freedom Under God in an annotated, Just Third Way Edition that
makes these points, and expanded on them in a new foreword and annotation to
explain things to today’s readers.
#30#